Of the Survival of Images. Memory and Mind by Henri Bergson
Of the Survival of Images. Memory and Mind by Henri Bergson

Of the Survival of Images. Memory and Mind

Henri Bergson * Track #3 On Matter and Memory

The music player is only available for users with at least 1,000 points.

Download "Of the Survival of Images. Memory and Mind"

Of the Survival of Images. Memory and Mind by Henri Bergson

Performed by
Henri Bergson

Of the Survival of Images. Memory and Mind Annotated

CHAPTER III
Of The Survival of Images.
Memory and Mind.

To sum up briefly the preceding chapters: we have distinguished three processes, pure memory, memory-image and perception, of which none of them in fa ct, occurs apart from the others. Percep­tion is never a mere contact of the mind with the object present; it is impregnated with memory-images which complete it as they interpret it. The memory-image, in its turn, partakes of the "pure memory, " which it begins to materialize, and of the perception in which it tends to embody itself: regarded from the latter point of view, it might be defined as a nascent perception. Lastly, pure memory, though independent in theory, manifests itself as a rule only in the colored and living image which reveals it. Symboliz­ing these three terms by the consecutive segments AB, BC, CD, of the same straight line AD, we may say that our thought describes this line in a single movement, which goes from A to 0, and that is impossible to say precisely where one of the terms ends and another begins.

In fact, this is just what consciousness bears witness to when­ever, in order to analyze memory, it follows the movement of memory at work. Whenever we are trying to recover a recollec­tion, to call up some period of our history, we become conscious of an act sui ganeris by which we detach ourselves from the present in order to replace ourselves, first, in the past in general, then, in a certain region of the past - a work of adjustment, something like the focusing of a camera. But our recollection still remains virtual; we simply prepare ourselves to receive it by adopting the appropriate attitude. Little by little it comes into view like a con­densing cloud; fr om the virtual state it passes into the actual; and as its outlines become more distinct and its surface takes on color, it tends to imitate perception. But it remains attached to the past by its deepest roots, and if, when once realized, it did not retain something of its original virtuality, if, being a present state, it were not also something which stands out distinct from the present, we should never know it for a memory.

The capital error of associationism is that it substitutes fo r this continuity of becoming, which is the living reality, a discontinu­ous multiplicity of elements, inert and juxtaposed. Just because each of the elements so constituted contains, by reason of its ori­gin, something of what precedes and also of what fo llows, it must take to our eyes the fo rm of a mixed and, so to speak, impure state. But the principle of associationism requires that each psy­chical state should be a kind of atom, a simple element. Hence the necessity fo r sacrificing, in each of the phases we have distin­guished, the unstable to the stable, that is to say, the beginning to the end. If we are dealing with perception, we are asked to see in it nothing but the agglomerated sensations which color it and to overlook the remembered images which fo rm its dim nucleus. If it is the remembered image that we are considering, we are bid­den to take it already made, realized in a weak perception, and to shut our eyes to the pure memory which this image has progres­sively developed. In the rivalry which associationism thus sets up between the stable and the unstable, perception is bound to expel the memory-image, and the memory-image to expel pure memory. And thus the pure memory disappears altogether. Associationism, cutting in two by a line MO, the totality of the progress AD, sees, in the part 00, only the sensations which terminate it and which have been supposed to constitute the whole of perception; yet it also reduces the part AO to the realized image which pure memory attains to as it expands. Psychical life, then, is entirely summed up in these two elements, sensation and image. And as, on the one hand, this theory drowns in the image the pure memory, which makes the image into an original state, and, on the other hand, brings the image yet closer to perception by putting into percep­tion, in advance, something of the image itself, it ends up by find­ing between these two states only a diffe rence of degree, or of intensity. Hence the distinction between strong states and weak states, of which the first are supposed to be set up by us as perceptions of the present, and the second (why, no man knows) as representa­tions of the past. But the truth is that we shall never reach the past unless we fr ankly place ourselves within it. Essentially virtual, it cannot be known as something past unless we fo llow and adopt the movement by which it expands into a present image, thus emerging fr om obscurity into the light of day. In vain do we seek its trace in anything actual and already realized: we might as well look fo r darkness beneath the light. This is, in fact, the error of associationism: placed in the actual, it exhausts itself in vain attempts to discover in a realized and present state the mark of its past origin, to distinguish memory from perception, and to erect into a diffe rence in kind that which it condemned in advance to be but a diffe rence of magnitude.

To picture is not to remember. No doubt a recollection, as it becomes actual, tends to live in an image; however, the converse is not true, and the image, pure and simple, will not be referred to the past unless, indeed, it was in the past that I sought it, thus following the continuous progress which brought it fr om darkness into light. This is what psychologists too often forget when they conclude, from the fa ct that a remembered sensation becomes more actual the more we dwell upon it, that the memory of the sensation is the sensation itself beginning to be. The fact which they allege is undoubtedly true: the more I strive to recall a past pain, the nearer I come to feeling it in reality. But this is easy to understand, since the progress of a memory precisely consists, as we have said, in its becoming materialized. The question is: was the memory of a pain, when it began, really pain? Because the hypnotized subject ends by feeling hot when he is repeatedly told that he is hot, it does not follow that the words of the suggestion were themselves hot. Neither must we conclude that, because the memory of a sensation prolongs itself into that very sensation, the memory was a nascent sensation: perhaps, indeed. this memory plays, with regard to the sensation which fo llows it, precisely the part of the hypnotizer who makes the suggestion. The argument we are criticizing, presented in this form, is then already of no value as proof; still, it is not yet a vicious argument because it profits by the incontestable truth that memory passes into something else by becoming actual. The absurdity becomes patent when the argument is inverted (although this ought to be legitimate on the hypothesis adopted), that is to say, when the intensity of the sensation is decreased instead of the intensity of pure memory being increased. For then, if the two states differ merely in degree, there should be a given moment at which the sensation changed into a memory. If the memory of an acute pain, for instance, is but a slight pain, inversely, an intense pain which I fe el, will end, as it grows less, by being an acute pain remembered. Now the moment will come, undoubtedly, when it is impossible fo r me to say whether what I fe el is a slight sensation, which I experience, or a slight sensation, which I imagine (and this is natural, because the memory-image is already partly sensation), but never will this weak state appear to me to be the memory of a strong state. Memory, then, is something quite diffe rent.

But the illusion which consists in establishing only a diffe r­ence of degree between memory and perception is more than a mere consequence of associationism, more than an accident in the history of philosophy. Its roots lie deep. It rests, in the last analysis, on a fa lse idea of the nature and of the object of external perception. We are bent on regarding perception as only an instruc­tion addressed to a pure spirit, as having a purely speculative inter­est. Then, as memory is itself essentially a knowledge of this kind, since its object is no longer present, we can only find between perception and memory a difference of degree - perceptions being then supposed to throw memories back into the past, and thus to reserve to themselves the present simply because right is might. But there is much more between past and present than a mere difference of degree. My present is that which interests me, which lives fo r me, and in a word, that which summons me to action; in contrast, my past is essentially powerless. We must dwell fu rther on this point. By contrasting it with present perception we shall better understand the nature of what we call "pure memory."

For we should endeavor in vain to characterize the memory of a past state unless we began by defining the concrete note, accepted by consciousness, of present reality. What is, fo r me, the present moment? The essence of time is that it goes by; time already gone by is the past, and we call the present the instant in which it goes by. But there can be no question here of a mathematical instant. No doubt there is an ideal present - a pure conception, the indivisi­ble limit which separates past from fu ture. But the real, concrete, live present - that of which I speak when I speak of my present perception - that present necessarily occupies a duration. Where then is this duration placed? Is it on the nearer or on the fu rther side of the mathematical point which I determine ideally when I think of the present instant? Quite evidently, it is both on this side and on that, and what I call "my present" has one fo ot in my past and another in my fu ture. In my past, first, because "the moment in which I am speaking is already fa r fr om me"; in my fu ture, next, because this moment is impending over the fu ture: it is to the fu ture that I am tending, and could I fix this indivisible present, this infinitesimal element of the curve of time, it is the direction of the fu ture that it would indicate. The psychical state, then, that I call "my present," must be both a perception of the immediate past and a determination of the immediate fu ture. Now the immediate past, in so fa r as it is perceived, is, as we shall see, sensation, since every sensation translates a very long succession of elementary vibrations, and the immediate fu ture, in so fa r as it is being determined, is action or movement. My present, then, is both sensation and movement; since my present fo rms an undi­vided whole, then the movement must be linked with the sensa­tion, must prolong it in action. Whence I conclude that my present consists in a joint system of sensations and movements. My pre­sent is, in its essence, sensori-motor.

This is to say that my present consists in the consciousness I have of my body. Having extension in space, my body experiences sensations and at the same time executes movements. Sensations and movements being localized at determined points of this extended body, there can only be, at a given moment, a single system of movements and sensations. That is why my present appears to me to be a thing absolutely determined, and contrast­ing with my past. Situated between the matter which influences it and that on which it has influence, my body is a center of action, the place where the impressions received choose intelligently the path they will fo llow to transform themselves into movements accomplished. Thus it, indeed, represents the actual state of my becoming, that part of my duration which is in process of growth. More generally, in that continuity of becoming which is reality itself, the present moment is constituted by the quasi-instantaneous section effected by our perception in the flowing mass, and this section is precisely that which we call the material world. Our body occupies its center; it is, in this material world, that part of which we directly fe el the flux; in its actual state the actuality of our present lies. If matter, so fa r as extended in space, is to be defined (as we believe it must) as a present which is always begin­ning again, inversely, our present is the very materiality of our existence, that is to say, a system of sensations and movements and nothing else. And this system is determined, unique fo r each moment of duration, just because sensations and movements occupy space, and because there cannot be in the same place several things at the same time. Why is it that it has been possible to misunder­stand so simple, so evident a truth, one which is, moreover, the very idea of common sense?

The reason lies simply in the fa ct that philosophers insist on regarding the difference between actual sensations and pure memory as a mere diffe rence in degree, and not in kind. In our view the diffe rence is radical. My actual sensations occupy definite por­tions of the surface of my body; pure memory, on the other hand, interests no part of my body. No doubt, it will beget sensations as it materializes, but at that very moment it will cease to be a memory and pass into the state of a present thing, something actually lived. I shall then only restore to it its character of memory by carrying myself back to the process by which I called it up, as it was vir­tual, fr om the depths of my past. It is just because I made it active that it has become actual, that is to say, a sensation capable of provoking movements. But most psychologists see in pure memory only a weakened perception, an assembly of nascent sensations. Having thus effaced, to begin with, all diffe rence in kind between sensation and memory, they are led by the logic of their hypothesis to materialize memory and to idealize sensation. They perceive memory only in the fo rm of an image, that is to say, already embod­ied in nascent sensations. Having thus attributed to it that which is essential to sensation, and refusing to see in the ideality of memory something distinct, something contrasted with sensation itself, they are fo rced, when they come back to pure sensation, to leave to it that ideality with which they have thus implicitly endowed nascent sensations. For if the past, which by hypothesis is no longer active, can subsist in the fo rm of a weak sensation, there must be sensations that are powerless. If pure memory, which by hypothe­sis interests no definite part of the body, is a nascent sensation, then sensation is not essentially localized in any point of the body. Hence the illusion that consists in regarding sensation as an ethe­real and unextended state which acquires extension and consoli­dates in the body by mere accident: an illusion which vitiates profoundly, as we have seen the theory of external perception and raises a great number of the questions at issue between the vari­ous metaphysics of matter. We must make up our minds to it: sensation is, in its essence, extended and localized; it is a source of movement. Pure memory, being inextensive and powerless, does not in any degree share the nature of sensation.

That which I call my present is my attitude with regard to the immediate fu ture; it is my impending action. My present is, then, sensori-motor. Of my past, that alone becomes image and, conse­quently, sensation, at least nascent, which can collaborate in that action, insert itself in that attitude, in a word make itself useful; but, fr om the moment that it becomes image, the past leaves the state of pure memory and coincides with a certain part of my present. Memory actualized in an image diffe rs, then, profoundly fr om pure memory. The image is a present state, and its sole share in the past is the memory from which it arose. Memory, on the contrary, powerless as long as it remains without utility, is pure fr om all admixture of sensation, is without attachment to the present, and is, consequently, unextended.

This radical powerlessness of pure memory is just what will enable us to understand how it is preserved in a latent state. With­out as yet going to the heart of the matter, we will confine our­selves to the remark that our unwillingness to conceive unconscious psychical states is due, above all, to the fa ct that we hold conscious­ness to be the essential property of psychical states: so a psychical state cannot, it seems, cease to be conscious without ceasing to exist. But if consciousness is but the characteristic note of the present, that is to say, of the actually lived, in short, of the active, then that which does not act may cease to belong to conscious­ness without therefore ceasing to exist in some manner. In other words, in the psychological domain, consciousness may not be the synonym of existence, but only of real action or of immediate efficacy; limiting thus the meaning of the term, we shall have less difficulty in representing to ourselves a psychical state which is unconscious, that is to say, ineffective. Whatever idea we may frame of consciousness in itself, such as it would be if it could work untrammeled, we cannot deny that, in a being which has bodily fu nctions, the chief office of consciousness is to preside over action and to enlighten choice. Therefore, it throws light on the imme­diate antecedents of the decision, and on those past recollections which can usefully combine with it; all else remains in shadow. But we find here once more, in a new fo rm, the ever-recurrent illusion which, throughout this work, we have endeavored to dis­pel. It is supposed that consciousness, even when linked with bodily fu nctions, is a faculty that is only accidentally practical and is directed essentially toward speculation. Then, since we cannot see what interest, devoted as it is supposed to be to pure knowl­edge, it would have in allowing any information that it possesses to escape, we fa il to understand why it refuses to throw light on something that was not entirely lost to it. From this we conclude that it can possess nothing more de jure than what it holds de fa cto, and that, in the domain of consciousness, all that is real is actual. But restore to consciousness its true role: there will no longer be any more reason to say that the past effaces itself as soon as perceived than there is to suppose that material objects cease to exist when we cease to perceive them.

We must insist on this last point, fo r here we have the central difficulty, and the source of the ambiguities which surround the problem of the unconscious. The idea of an unconscious representation is clear, despite current prejudice; we may even say that we make constant use of it, and that there is no conception more fa miliar to common sense. For everyone admits that the images actually present to our perception are not the whole of matter. But, on the other hand, what can be a nonperceived material object, an image not imagined, unless it is a kind of unconscious mental state? Beyond the walls of your room, which you perceive at this moment, there are the adjoining rooms, then the rest of the house, finally the street and the town in which you live. It signifies little to which theory of matter you adhere; realist or idealist, you are evi­dently thinking, when you speak of the town, of the street, of the other rooms in the house, of so many perceptions absent from your consciousness and yet given outside of it. They are not cre­ated as your consciousness receives them; they existed, then, in some manner, and since, by hypothesis, your consciousness did not apprehend them, how could they exist in themselves unless in the unconscious state? How comes it then that an existence out­side of consciousness appears clear to us in the case of objects, but obscure when we are speaking of the subject? Our perceptions, actual and virtual, extend along two lines, the one horizontal, AB, which contains all simultaneous objects in space, the other verti­cal, cr, on which are ranged our successive recollections set out in time. The point I, at the intersection of the two lines, is the only one actually given to consciousness. Whence comes it that we do not hesitate to posit the reality of the whole line AB, although it remains unperceived, while, on the contrary, of the line eI, the present I which is actually perceived is the only point which appears to us really to exist? There are, at the bottom of this radical dis­tinction between the two series, temporal and spatial, so many confused or half-formed ideas, so many hypotheses devoid of any speculative value, that we cannot all at once make an exhaustive analysis of them. In order to unmask the illusion entirely, we should have to seek its origin and fo llow through all its windings, the double movement by which we come to assume objective reali­ties without relation to consciousness, and states of conscious­ness without objective reality - space thus appearing to preserve indefinitely the things which are there juxtaposed, while time in its advance devours the states which succeed each other within it. Part of this work has been done in our first chapter, where we discussed objectivity in general; another part will be dealt with in the last pages of this book, where we shall speak of the idea of matter. We confine ourselves here to a few essential points.

Figure 3

First, the objects ranged along the line AB represent to our eyes what we are going to perceive, while the line CI contains only that which has already been perceived. Now the past has no longer any interest for us; it has exhausted its possible action or will only recover an influence by borrowing the vitality of the present perception. The immediate future, on the contrary, con­sists in an impending action, in an energy not yet spent. The unper­ceived part of the material universe, big with promises and threats, has then for us a reality which the actually unperceived periods of our past existence cannot and should not possess. But this dis­tinction, which is entirely relative to practical utility and to the material needs of life, takes in our minds the more and more marked form of a metaphysical distinction.

We have shown that the objects which surround us represent, in varying degrees, an action which we can accomplish upon things . or which we must experience from them. The date of fu lfilment of this possible action is indicated by the greater or lesser remote­ness of the corresponding object, so that distance in space mea­sures the proximity of a threat or of a promise in time. Thus space fu rnishes us at once with the diagram of our near fu ture, and, as this fu ture must recede indefinitely, space which symbolizes it has fo r its property to remain, in its immobility, indefinitely open. Hence the immediate horizon given to our perception appears to us to be necessarily surrounded by a wider circle, existing though unperceived, this circle itself implying yet another outside it and so on, ad infinitum. It is, then, of the essence of our actual per­ception, inasmuch as it is extended, to be always only a content in relation to a vaster, even an unlimited, experience which con­tains it; this experience, absent from our consciousness, since it spreads beyond the perceived horizon, nevertheless, appears to be actually given. But while we fe el ourselves to be dependent upon these material objects which we thus erect into present reallues, our memories, on the contrary, inasmuch as they are past, are so much dead weight that we carry with us, and by which we prefer to imagine ourselves unencumbered. The same instinct, in virtue of which we open out space indefinitely before us, prompts us to shut off time behind us as it flows. And while reality, in so fa r as it is extended, appears to us to overpass infinitely the bounds of our perception, in our inner life that alone seems to us to be real which begins with the present moment; the rest is practically abol­ished. Then, when a memory reappears in consciousness, it pro­duces on us the effect of a ghost whose mysterious apparition must be explained by special causes. In truth, the adherence of this memory to our present condition is exactly comparable to the adherence of unperceived objects to those objects which we per­ceive; and the unconscious plays in each case a similar part.

But we have great difficulty in representing the matter to our­selves in this way because we have fa llen into the habit of empha­sizing the differences and, on the contrary, of slurring over the resemblances, between the series of objects simultaneously set out in space and that of states successively developed in time. In the first, the terms condition each other in a manner which is entirely determined, so that the appearance of each new term may be fo re­seen. Thus I know, when I leave my room, what other rooms I shall go through. However, my memories present themselves in an order which is apparently capricious. The order of the repre­sentations is then necessary in the one case, contingent in the other; it is this necessity which I hypostatize, as it were, when I speak of the existence of objects outside of all consciousness. If I see no inconvenience in supposing, given the totality of objects which I do not perceive, it is because the strictly determined order of these objects lends to them the appearance of a chain, of which my pre­sent perception is only one link. This link communicates its actu­ality to the rest of the chain. But, if we look at the matter closely, we shall see that our memories form a chain of the same kind, and that our character, always present in all our decisions, is indeed the actual synthesis of all our past states. In this epitomized fo rm our previous psychical life exists fo r us even more than the exter­nal world, of which we never perceive more than a very small part, whereas, on the contrary, we use the whole of our lived experi­ence. It is true that we possess merely a digest of it, and that our fo rmer perceptions, considered as distinct individualities, seem to us to have completely disappeared or to appear again only at the bidding of their caprice. But this semblance of complete destruction or of capricious revival is due merely to the fa ct that actual consciousness accepts at each moment the useful and rej ects in the same breath the superfluous. Ever bent upon action, it can only materialize those of our fo rmer perceptions which can ally themselves with the present perception to take a share in the final decision. If it is necessary, when I would manifest my will at a given point of space, that my consciousness should go successively through those intermediaries or those obstacles of which the sum constitutes what we call distance in space, "So, on the other hand, it is useful, in order to throw light on this action, that my conscious­ness should jump the interval of time which separates the actual situation fr om a fo rmer one which resembles it; and as conscious­ness goes back to the earlier date at a bound, all the intermediate past escapes its hold. The same reasons, then, which cause our perceptions to range themselves in strict continuity in space, cause our memories to be illumined discontinuously in time. We have not, in regard to objects unperceived in space and unconscious memories in time, to do with two radically diffe rent fo rms of exis­tence, but the exigencies of action are the inverse in the one case of what they are in the other.

But here we come to the capital problem of existence, a prob­lem we can only glance at, fo r otherwise it would lead us step by step into the heart of metaphysics. We will merely say that with regard to matters of experience - which alone concern us here - existence appears to imply two conditions taken together: (1) presentation in consciousness and (2) the logical or casual con­nection of that which is so presented with what precedes and with what fo llows. The reality fo r us of a psychical state or of a material object consists in the double fa ct that our consciousness perceives them and that they fo rm part of a series, temporal or spatial, of which the elements determine each other. But these two condi­tions admit of degrees, and it is conceivable that, though both are necessary, they may be unequally fu lfilled. Thus, in the case of actual internal states, the connection is less close, and the deter­mination of the present by the past, leaving ample room fo r con­tingency, has not the character of a mathematical derivation -but then, presentation in consciousness is perfect, an actual psy­chical state yielding the whole of its content in the act itself, whereby we perceive it. On the contrary, if we are dealing with external objects it is the connection which is perfect, since these objects obey necessary laws; but then the other condition, pre­sentation in consciousness, is never more than partially fu lfilled, fo r the material object, just because of the multitude of unper­ceived elements by which it is linked with all other objects, appears to enfold within itself and to hide behind it infinitely more than it allows to be seen. We ought to say, then, that existence, in the empirical sense of the word, always implies conscious apprehen­sion and regular connection; both at the same time, although in diffe rent degrees. But our intellect, of which the fu nction is to establish clear-cut distinctions, does not so understand things. Rather than admit the presence in all cases of the two elements mingled in varying proportions, it prefers to dissociate them, and thus attribute to external objects, on the one hand, and to inter­nal states, on the other hand, two radically diff erent modes of existence, each characterized by the exclusive presence of the condition which should be regarded as merely preponderating. Then the existence of psychical states is assumed to consist entirely in their apprehension by consciousness, and that of external phenomena, entirely also, in the strict order of their concomitance and their succession. Whence the impossibility ofleaving to material objects, existing, but unperceived, the smallest share in consciousness, and to internal unconscious states the smallest share in existence. We have shown, at the beginning of this book, the consequences of the first illusion: it ends by fa lsifying our representation of mat­ter. The second illusion, complementary to the first, vitiates our conception of mind by casting over the idea of the unconscious an artificial obscurity. The whole of our past psychical life condi­tions our present state, without being its necessary determinant; whole, also, it reveals itself in our character, although none of its past states manifests itself explicitly in character. Ta ken together, these two conditions assure to each one of the past psychological states a real, though an unconscious, existence.

But we are so much accustomed to reverse, fo r the sake of action, the real order of things, we are so strongly obsessed by images drawn fr om space, that we cannot hinder ourselves fr om asking where memories are stored up. We understand that physico­chemical phenomena take place in the brain, that the brain is in the body, the body in the air which surrounds it, etc.; but the past, once achieved, if it is retained, where is it? To locate it in the cerebral substance, in the state of molecular modification, seems clear and simple enough because then we have a receptacle, actu­ally given, which we have only to open in order to let the latent images flow into consciousness. But ifthe brain cannot serve such a purpose, in what warehouse shall we store the accumulated images? We fo rget that the relation of container to content bor­rows its apparent clearness and universality from the necessity laid upon us of always opening out space in front of us and of always closing duration behind us. Because it has been shown that one thing is within another, the phenomenon of its preservation is not thereby made any clearer. We may even go fu rther: let us admit fo r a moment that the past survives in the fo rm of a memory stored in the brain; it is then necessary that the brain, in order to pre­serve the memory, should preserve itself. But the brain, insofar as it is an image extended in space, never occupies more than the present moment: it constitutes, with all the rest of the material universe, an ever-renewed section of universal becoming. Either, then, you must suppose that this universe dies and is born again miraculously at each moment of duration, or you must attribute to it that continuity of existence which you deny to conscious­ness, and make ofits past a reality which endures and is prolonged into its present. So that you have gained nothing by depositing the memories in matter, and you find yourself, on the contrary, compelled to extend to the totality of the states of the material world that complete and independent survival of the past which you have just refused to psychical states. This survival of the past per se fo rces itself upon philosophers, then, under one fo rm or another; the difficulty that we have in conceiving it comes simply from the fa ct that we extend to the series of memories, in time, that obligation of containing and being contained which applies only to the collection of bodies instantaneously perceived in space. The fu ndamental illusion consists in transferring to duration itself, in its continuous flow, the fo rm of the instantaneous sections which we make in it.

But how can the past, which, by hypothesis, has ceased to be, preserve itself? Have we not here a real contradiction? We reply that the question is just whether the past has ceased to exist or whether it has simply ceased to be useful. Yo u define the present in an arbitrary manner as th at which is, whereas the present is simply what is being made. Nothing is less than the present moment, if you understand by that the indivisible limit which divides the past fr om the fu ture. When we think this present as going to be, it exists not yet, and when we think it as existing, it is already past. If, on the other hand, what you are considering is the concrete present such as it is actually lived by consciousness, we may say that this present consists, in large measure, in the immediate past. In the fraction of a second which covers the briefest possible per­ception of light, billions of vibrations have taken place, of which the first is separated from the last by an interval which is enor­mously divided. Yo ur perception, however instantaneous, consists then in an incalculable multitude of remembered elements; in truth, every perception is already memory. Practically, we perceive only the past, the pure present being the invisible progress of the past gnawing into the fu ture.

Consciousness, then, illumines, at each moment of time, that immediate part of the past which, impending over the fu ture, seeks to realize and to associate with it. Solely preoccupied in thus determining an undetermined fu ture, consciousness may shed a little of its light on those of our states, more remote in the past, which can be usefully combined with our present state, that is to say, with our immediate past: the rest remains in the dark. It is in this illuminated part of our history that we remain seated, in virtue of the fu ndamental law of life, which is a law of action: hence the difficulty we experience in conceiving memories which are preserved in the shadow. Our reluctance to admit the integ­ral survival of the past has its origin, then, in the very bent of our psychical life -an unfolding of states wherein our interest prompts us to look at that which is unrolling, and not at that which is entirely unrolled.

So we return, after a long digression, to our point of depar­ture. There are, we have said, two memories which are profoundly distinct: the one, fixed in the organism, is nothing else but the complete set of intelligently constructed mechanisms which ensure the appropriate reply to the various possible demands. This memory enables us to adapt ourselves to the present situation; through it the actions to which we are subject prolong themselves into reac­tions that are sometimes accomplished, sometimes merely nascent, but always more or less appropriate. Habit rather than memory, it acts our past experience but does not call up its image. The other is the true memory. Coextensive with consciousness, it retains and ranges alongside of each other all our states in the order in which they occur, leaving to each fa ct its place and, consequently, marking its date, truly moving in the past and not, like the first, in an ever renewed present. But, in marking the profound distinc­tion between these two fo rms of memory, we have not shown their connecting link. Above the body, with its mechanisms which sym­bolize the accumulated effort of past actions, the memory which imagines and repeats has been left to hang, as it were, suspended in the void. Now, if it be true that we never perceive anything but our immediate past, if our consciousness of the present is already memory, the two terms which had been separated to begin with cohere closely together. Seen from this new point of view, indeed, our body is nothing but that part of our representation which is ever being born again, the part always present, or rather that which, at each moment, is just past. Itself an image, the body cannot store up images, since it fo rms a part of the images, and this is why it is a chimerical enterprise to seek to localize past or even present per­ceptions in the brain: they are not in it; it is the brain that is in them. But this special image which persists in the midst of the others, and which I call my body, constitutes at every moment, as we have said, a section of the universal becoming. It is then the place of passage of the movements received and thrown back, a hyphen, a connecting link between the things which act upon me and the things upon which I act - the seat, in a word, of the sensori­motor phenomena. If I represent by a cone SAB, the totality of the recollections accumulated in my memory, the base AB, situ­ated in the past, remains motionless, while the summit S, which indicates at all times my present, moves fo rward unceasingly, and unceasingly also touches the moving plane P of my actual repre­sentation of the universe. At S, the image of the body is concen­trated, and, since it belongs to the plane P, this image does but receive and restore actions emanating fr om all the images of which the plane is composed.

Figure 4

The bodily memory, made up of the sum of the sensori-motor systems organized by habit, is then a quasi-instantaneous memory to which the true memory of the past serves as base. Since they are not two separate things, since the first is only, as we have said, the pointed end, ever moving, inserted by the second in the shift­ing plane of experience, it is natural that the two fu nctions should lend each other a mutual support. So, on the one hand, the memory of the past offers to the sensori-motor mechanisms all the recol­lections capable of guiding them in their task and of giving to the motor reaction the direction suggested by the lessons of experience. It is in just this that the associations of contiguity and like­ness consist. But, on the other hand, the sensori-motor apparatus fu rnish to ineffective, that is unconscious, memories, the means of taking on a body, of materializing themselves, in short of bee om­ing present. For, that a recollection should reappear in conscious­ness, it is necessary that it should descend from the heights of pure memory down to the precise point where action is taking place. In other words, it is fr om the present that the appeal to which memory responds comes, and it is from the sensori-motor ele­ments of present action that a memory borrows the warmth which gives it life.

Is it not by the constancy of this agreement, by the precision with which these two complementary memories insert themselves each into the other, that we recognize a "well-balanced" mind, that is to say, in fact, a man nicely adapted to life? The characteris­tic of the man of action is the promptitude with which he sum­mons to the help of a given situation all the memories which have reference to it; yet it is also the insurmountable barrier which encounters, when they present themselves on the threshold of his consciousness, memories that are useless or indiffe rent. To live only in the present, to respond to a stimulus by the immediate reaction which prolongs it, is the mark of the lower animals: the man who proceeds in this way is a man of impulse. But he who lives in the past fo r the mere pleasure ofliving there, and in whom recollections emerge into the light of consciousness without any advantage fo r the present situation, is hardly better fitted fo r action: here we have no man of impulse, but a dreamer. Between these two extremes lives the happy disposition of memory docile enough to fo llow with precision all the outlines of the present situation, but energetic enough to resist all other appeal. Good sense, or practical sense, is probably nothing but this.

The extraordinary development of spontaneous memory in most children is due to the fa ct that they have not yet persuaded their memory to remain bound up with their conduct. They usually follow the impression of the moment, and as with them action does not bow to the suggestions of memory, so neither are their recollections limited to the necessities of action. They seem to retain with greater facilit y only because they remember with less discernment. The apparent diminution of memory, as intellect develops, is then due to the growing organization of recollections with acts. Thus conscious memory loses in range what it gains in fo rce of penetration: it had at first the fa cility of the memory of dreams, but then it was actually dreaming. Indeed we observe this same exaggeration of spontaneous memory in men whose intel­lectual development hardly goes beyond that of childhood. A mis­sionary, after preaching a long sermon to some African savages, heard one of them repeat it textually, with the same gestures, from beginning to end.1

But, if almost the whole of our past is hidden fr om us because it is inhibited by the necessities of present action, it will find strength to cross the threshold of consciousness in all cases where we renounce the interests of effective action to replace ourselves, so to speak, in the life of dreams. Sleep, natural or artificial, brings about an indiffe rence of just this kind. It has been recently sug­gested that in sleep there is an interruption ofthe contact between the nervous elements, motor and sensory.2 Even if we do not accept this ingenious hypothesis, it is impossible not to see in sleep a relaxing, even if only fu nctional, of the tension of the nervous system, ever ready, during waking hours, to prolong by an appro­priate reaction the stimulation received. Now the exaltation of the memory in certain dreams and in certain somnambulistic states is well known. Memories, which we believed abolished, then reap­pear with striking completeness; we live over again, in all their detail, fo rgotten scenes of childhood; we speak languages which we no longer even remember to have learned. But there is nothing more instructive in this regard than what happens in cases of sud­den suffocation, in men drowned or hanged. Such a man, when brought to life again, states that he saw, in a very short time, all the fo rgotten events of his life passing before him with great rapidity, with their smallest circumstances and in the very order in which they occurred.3

A human being who should dream his life instead of living it would no doubt thus keep before his eyes at each moment the infinite multitude of the details of his past history. And, conversely, the man who should repudiate this memory with all that it begets would be continually acting his life instead of truly representing it to himself: a conscious automaton, he would fo llow the lead of useful habits which prolong into an appropriate reaction the stim­ulation received. The first would never rise above the particular, or even above the individual; leaving to each image its date in time and its position in space, he would see wherein it diffe rs fr om others and not how it resembles them. The other, always swayed by habit, would only distinguish in any situation that aspect in which it practically resembles fo rmer situations; incapable, doubt­less, of thinkinB universals, since every general idea implies the rep­resentation, at least virtual, of a number of remembered images, he would, nevertheless, move in the universal, habit being to action what generality is to thought. But these two extreme states, the one of an entirely contemplative memory which apprehends only the singular in its vision, the other of a purdy motor memory which stamps the note of generality on its action , are really separate and are fu lly visible only in exceptional cases. In normal life they are interpenetrating, so that each has to abandon some part of its ori­ginal purity. The first reveals itself in the recollection of diffe r­ences, the second in the perception of resemblances: at the meeting of the two currents appears the general idea.

We are not concerned here to settle once fo r all the whole ques­tion of general ideas. Some have not originated in perception alone, and have but a very distant connection with material objects. We will leave these on one side and consider only those general ideas that are fo unded on what we have called the perception of simi­larity. We will try to fo llow pure memory, integral memory, in the continuous effort which it makes to insert itself into motor habit. In this way we may throw more light upon the office and nature of this memory, and perhaps make clearer, at the same time, by regard­ing them in this particular aspect, the two equally obscure notions of resemblance and of generality.

If we consider as closely as possible the difficulties of a psy­chological order which surround the problem of general ideas, we shall come, we believe , to enclose them in this circle: to gen­eralize, it is first of all necessary to abstract, but to abstract to any purpose we must already know how to generalize. Round this cir­cle gravitate, consciously or unconsciously, nominalism and con­ceptualism, each doctrine having in its favor mainly the insufficiency of the other. The nominalists, retaining of the general idea only its extension, see in it merely an open and unlimited series of individual objects. The unity of the idea can then, for them, con­sist only in the identity of the symbol by which we designate indif­fe rently all these distinct objects. According to them, we begin by perceiving a thing, and then we assign to it a word: this word, backed by the fa culty or the habit of extending itself to an unlim­ited number of other things, then sets up fo r a general idea. But, in order that the word should extend and yet limit itself to the objects which it designates, it is necessary that these objects should offe r us resemblances which, when we compare them, shall dis­tinguish them fr om all the objects to which the word does not apply. Generalization does not, consequently, occur without our taking into account qualities that have been fo und to be common and therefore considered in the abstract; from step to step, nomi­nalism is thus led to define the general idea by its intention and not merely by its extension, as it set out to do. It is just fr om this intention that conceptualism starts; the intellect, in this theory, resolves the superficial unity of the individual into diffe rent quali­ties, each of which, isolated from the individual who limited it, becomes by that very isolation representative of a genus. Instead of regarding each genus as including actually a multiplicity of objects, it is now maintained, on the contrary, that each object involves potentially, and as so many qualities which it holds captive, a mul­tiplicity of genera. But the question before us is whether individ­ual qualities, even isolated by an effort of abstraction, do not remain individual, and whether, to make them into genera, a new effort of the mind is not required, by which it first bestows on each quality a name, and then collects under this name a multitude of individual objects. The whiteness of a lily is not the whiteness of a snowfield; they remain, even as isolated fr om the snow and the lily, snow-white or lily-white. They only fo rego their individual­ity if we consider their likeness in order to give them a common name; then, applying this name to an unlimited number of sim­ilar objects, we throw back upon the quality, by a sort of ricochet, the generality which the word went out to seek in its application to things. But, reasoning in this way, do we not return to the point of view of extension, which we just now abandoned? We are then, in truth, revolving in a circle, nominalism leading us to conceptu­al ism, and conceptualism bringing us back to nominalism. Gen­eralization can only be effected by extracting common qualities; however, that qualities should appear common, they must have already been subjected to a process of generalization.

Now, when we get to the bottom of these two opposite theo­ries, we find in them a common postulate; each will have it that we start fr om the perception of individual objects. The first composes the genus by an enumeration; the second disengages it by an analysis; but it is upon individuals, considered as so many realities given to immediate intuition, that both analysis and enumeration are supposed to bear. This is the postulate. In spite of its apparent obviousness, we must expect to find, and we do indeed find, that experience belies it.

A priori, indeed, we may expect the clear distinction of indi­vidual objects to be a luxury of perception, just as the clear repre­sentation of general ideas is a refinement of the intellect. The full conception of genera is no doubt proper to human thought; it demands an effort of reflection, by which we expunge fr om a rep­resentation the details of time and place. But the reflection on these details - a reflection without which the individuality of objects would escape us - presupposes a fac ulty of noticing dif­fe rences, and therefore, a memory of images, which is certainly the privilege of man and of the higher animals. It would seem, then, that we start neither from the perception of the individual nor from the conception of the genus, but from an intermediate knowledge, from a confused sense of the strikin8 quality or of resem­blance: this sense, equally remote from generality fu lly conceived and from individuality clearly perceived, begets both of them by a process of dissociation. Reflective analysis clarifies it into the general idea; discriminative memory solidifies it into a percep­tion of the individual.

But this will be more clearly evident if we go back to the purely utilitarian origin of our perception of things. That which inter­ests us in a given situation, that which we are likely to grasp in it first, is the side by which it can respond to a tendency or a need. But a need goes straight to the resemblance or quality; it cares little fo r individual differences. To this discernment of the useful we .may surmise that the perception of animals is, in most cases confined. It is grass in 8enerai which attracts the herbivorous animal: the color and the smell of grass, fe lt and experienced as fo rces (we do not go so fa r as to say, thought as qualities or genera), are the sole immediate data of its external perception. On this back­ground of generality or of resemblance the animal's memory may show up contrasts fr om which will issue diffe rentiations; it will then distinguish one countryside fr om another, one field from another field; but this is, we repeat, the superfluity of perception, not a necessary part. It may be urged that we are only throwing the problem fu rther back, that we are merely relegating to the unconscious the process by which similarity is discovered and gen­era are constituted. But we relegate nothing to the unconscious fo r the very simple reason that it is not, in our opinion, an effort of a psychological nature which here disengages similarity; this similarity acts objectively like a force and provokes reactions that are identical in virtue of the purely physical law which requires that the same general effects should fo llow the same profound causes. Hydrochloric acid always acts in the same way upon car­bonate of lime whether in the fo rm of marble or of chalk yet we do not say that the acid perceives in the various species the char­acteristic fe atures of the genus. Now there is no essential diffe r­ence between the process by which this acid picks out fr om the salt its base and the act of the plant which invariably extracts fr om the most diverse soils those elements that serve to nourish it. Make one more step; imagine a rudimentary consciousness such as that of an amoeba in a drop of water: it will be sensible of the resem­blance, and not of the diffe rence, in the various organic substances which it can assimilate. In short, we can fo llow from the mineral to the plant, from the plant to the simplest conscious beings, fr om the animal to man, the progress of the operation by which things and beings seize fr om their surroundings that which attracts them, that which interests them practically, without needing any effort of abstraction, simply because the rest of their surroundings takes no hold upon them: this similarity of reaction fo llowing actions superficially diffe rent is the germ which the human conscious­ness develops into general ideas.

Consider, indeed, the purpose and fu nction of our nervous sys­tem as far as we can infer them from its structure. We see a great variety of mechanisms of perception, all bound, through the inter­mediary of the centers, to the same motor apparatus. Sensation is unstable; it can take the most varied shades; the motor mecha­nism, on the contrary, once set going, will invariably work in the same way. We may then suppose perceptions as diffe rent as possi­ble in their superficial details: if only they are continued by the same motor reactions, if the organism can extract fr om them the same useful effects, if they impress upon the body the same atti­tude, something common will issue from them, and the general idea will have been fe lt and passively experienced, before being represented. Here then we escape at last fr om the circle in which we at first appeared to be confined. In order to generalize, we said, we have to abstract similarity, but in order to disengage simi­larity usefully we must already know how to generalize. There really is no circle because the similarity, from which the mind starts when it first begins the work of abstraction, is not the simi­larity at which the mind arrives when it consciously generalizes. That fr om which it starts is a similarity fe lt and lived, or, if you prefer the expression, a similarity which is automatically acted. That to which it returns is a similarity intelligently perceived, or thought. And it is precisely in the course of this progress that are built up, by the double effort of the understanding and of the memory, the perception of individuals and the conception of gen­era -memory grafting distinctions upon resemblances which have been spontaneously abstracted, the understanding disengaging fr om the habit of resemblances the clear idea of generality. This idea of generality was, in the beginning, only our consciousness of a likeness of attitude in a diversity of situations; it was habit itself, mount­ing from the sphere of movement to that of thought. But fr om genera so sketched out mechanically by habit we have passed by an effort of reflection upon this very process, to the general idea of genus; and when that idea has been once constituted, we have con­structed (this time voluntarily) an unlimited number of general notions. It is not necessary here to fo llow the intellect into the detail of this construction. It is enough to say that the understand­ing, imitating the effort of nature, has also set up motor appara­tuses, artificial in this case, to make a limited number of them answer to an unlimited number of individual objects: the assem­blage of these mechanisms is articulate speech.

Yet these two divergent operations of the mind, the one by which it discerns individuals, the other by which it constructs genera, are far fr om demanding the same effort or progressing with the same rapidity. The first, requiring only the intervention of memory, takes place from the outset of our experience; the sec­ond goes on indefinitely without ever reaching its goal. The first emerges in the fo rmation of stable images, which in their turn are stored up in memory; the second comes out in representations that are unstable and evanescent. We must dwell on this last point, fo r we touch here an essential problem of mental life.

The essence of the general idea, in fa ct, is to be unceasingly going backwards and fo rwards between the plane of action and that of pure memory. Let us refer once more to the diagram we traced above. At S is the present perception which I have of my body, that is to say, of a certain sensori-motor equilibrium. Over the surface of the base AB are spread, we may say, my recollec­tions in their totality. Within the cone so determined, the general idea oscillates continually between the summit S and the base AB. In S, it would take the clearly defined fo rm of a bodily attitude or of an uttered word; at AB, it would wear the aspect, no less defined, of the thousand individual images into which its fr agile unity would break up. And that is why a psychology which abides by the already done, which considers only that which is made and ignores that which is in the making, will never perceive in this movement anything more than the two extremities between which it oscillates; it makes the general idea coincide sometimes with the action which manifests it or the word which expresses it and at other times with the multitudinous images, unlimited in num­ber, which are its equivalent in memory. But the truth is that the general idea escapes us as soon as we try to fix it at either of the two extremities. It consists in the double current which goes fr om the one to the other - always ready either to crystallize into uttered words or to evaporate into memories.

Figure 5

This amounts to saying that between the sensori-motor mecha­nisms figured by the point S and the totality of the memories dis­posed in AB there is room, as we indicated in the preceding chapter, fo r a thousand repetitions of our psychical life, figured by as many sections A/B' ,A"B", etc., of the same cone. We tend to scatter ourselves over AB in the measure that we detach ourselves from our sensory and motor state to live in the life of dreams; we tend to concentrate ourselves in S in the measure that we attach our­selves more firmly to the present reality, responding by motor reac­tions to sensory stimulation. In point of fa ct, the normal self never stays in either ofthese extreme positions; it moves between them, adopts in turn the positions corresponding to the intermediate sections, or, in other words, gives to its representations just enough image and just enough idea fo r them to be able to lend useful aid to the present action.

From this conception of the lower mental life, the laws of the association of ideas can be deduced. But, before we deal with this point, we must first show the insufficiency of the current theories of association.

That every idea which arises in the mind has a relation of simi­larity or of contiguity with the previous mental state, we do not dispute; but a statement of the kind neither throws light on the mechanism of association nor, indeed, does it really tell us any­thing at all. For we should seek in vain fo r two ideas which have not some point of resemblance or which do not touch each other somewhere. To take similarity first: however profound are the dif­fe rences which separate two images, we shall always find, if we go back high enough, a common genus to which they belong, and, consequently, a resemblance which may serve as a connecting link between them. And, in regard to contiguity, a perception A, as we said before, will not evoke "by contiguity" a fo rmer image B, unless it recalls to us first an image A' , which is like it, because it is the recollection A', and not the perception A, which really touches B in memory. However distant, then, we suppose the terms A and B fr om each other, a relation of contiguity can always be fo und between them, provided that the intercalated term A' bears a sufficiently fa rfetched resemblance to A. This is as much as to say that between any two ideas chosen at random there is always a resemblance, and always, even, contiguity, so that, when we dis­cover a relation of contiguity or of resemblance between two suc­cessive ideas, we have in no way explained why the one evokes the other.

What we really need to discover is how a choice is effected among an infinite number of recollections which all resemble in some way the present perception, and why only one of them -this rather than that -emerges into the light of consciousness. But this is just what associationism cannot tell us, because it has made ideas and images into independent entities floating, like the atoms ofEpicurus, in an inward space, drawing near to each other when chance brings them within the sphere of mutual attraction. And if we try to get to the bottom of the doctrine on this point, we find that its error is that it overly intellectualizes ideas: it attri­butes to them a purely speculative role, believes that they exist fo r themselves and not fo r us, and overlooks the relation which they bear to the activity of the will. If memories move about indif­fe rently in a consciousness that is both lifeless and shapeless, there is no reason why the present perception should prefer and attract anyone of them: we can only, in that case, note the conjunction, when once it has taken place, and speak of similarity or of conti­guity - which is merely, at bottom, to express in vague terms that our mental states have affinities fo r one another.

But even of this affinity, which takes the double fo rm of conti­guity and of similarity, associationism can fu rnish no explanation. The general tendency to associate remains as obscure fo r us, if we adhere to this doctrine, as the particular fo rms of association. Hav­ing stiffe ned individual memory-images into ready-made things, given cut-and-dry in the course of our mental life, associationism is reduced to bringing in, between these objects, mysterious attrac­tions, of which it is not even possible to say beforehand, as of physical attraction, by what effects they will manifest themselves. For why should an image which is, by hypothesis, self-sufficient, seek to accrue to itself others either similar or given in contiguity with it? The truth is that this independent image is a late and artificial product of the mind. In fa ct, we perceive the resemblance before we perceive the individuals which resemble each other; and, in an aggregate of contiguous parts, we perceive the whole before the parts. We go on from similarity to similar objects, embroider­ing upon the similarity, as on their common stuff, or canvas, the variety of individual differences. And we go on also from the whole to the parts, by a process of decomposition the law of which will appear later, a process which consists in breaking up, fo r the greater convenience of practical life, the continuity of the real. Associa­tion, then, is not the primary fa ct: dissociation is what we begin with, and the tendency of every memory to gather to itself others must be explained by the natural return of the mind to the undi­vided unity of perception.

But here we discover the radical vice of associationsim. Given a present perception which fo rms by turns, with diffe rent recol­lections, several associations one after another, there are two ways, as we said, of conceiving the mechanism of this association. We may suppose that the perception remains identical with itself, a true psychical atom which gathers to itself others just as these happen to be passing by. This is the point of view of associationism. But there is also another - precisely the one which we have indi­cated in our theory of recognition. We have supposed that our entire personality, with the totality of our recollections, is pre­sent, undivided within our actual perception. Then, if this per­ception evokes in turn different memories, it is not by a mechanical adjunction of more and more numerous elements which, while remaining unmoved, it attracts around it, but rather by an expan­sion of the entire consciousness which, spreading out over a larger area, discovers the fu ller detail of its wealth. So a nebulous mass, seen through more and more powerful telescopes, resolves itself into an ever greater number of stars. In the first hypothesis (in favor of which there is little but its apparent simplicity and its analogy with a misunderstood physical atomism), each recollec­tion is a fixed and independent being, of which we can neither say why it seeks to accrue to itself others, nor how it chooses, among a thousand memories which should have equal rights, those with which to associate itself in virtue of similarity or contiguity. We must suppose that ideas jostle each other at random, or that they exert among themselves mysterious fo rces, and, moreover, we have against us the witness of consciousness, which never shows us psy­chical fa cts floating as independent entities. From the second point of view, we merely state a fact, viz., that psychic fa cts are bound up with each other, and are always given together to immediate consciousness as an undivided whole which reflection alone cuts up into distinct fragments. What we have to explain, then, is no longer the cohesion of internal states, but the double movement of contraction and expansion by which consciousness narrows or enlarges the development of its content. But this movement, we shall see, is the result of the fu ndamental needs of life; and we shall also see why the "associations," which we appear to fo rm in the course of this movement, correspond to all the possible degrees of so-called contiguity and resemblance.

Let us, fo r a moment, suppose our psychical life reduced to sensori-motor fu nctions alone. In other words, suppose ourselves placed in Figure 5 on page 162 at point S, which corresponds to the greatest possible simplification of our mental life. In this state every perception spontaneously prolongs itself into appropriate reactions, fo r analogous fo rmer perceptions have set up more or less complex motor apparatus, which only await a recurrence of the same appeal in order to enter into play. Now there is, in this mechanism, an association of simplicity, since the present percep­tion acts in virtue of its likeness to past perceptions; there is also an association of contiguity, since the movements which fo llowed those fo rmer perceptions reproduce themselves and may even bring in their train a vast number of actions coordinate with the first. Here then we seize association of similarity and association of con­tiguity at their very source, and at a point where they are almost confounded in one - not indeed thought, but acted and lived. They are not contingent fo rms of our psychical life; they repre­sent the two complementary aspects of one and the same fu nda­mental tendency, the tendency of every organism to extract from a given situation that in it which is useful, and to store up the eventual reaction in the fo rm of a motor habit, that it may serve other situations of the same kind.

Let us jump now to the other extremity of our mental life, and, fo llowing our line of thought, go from the psychical exis­tence which is merely "acted," to that which is exclusively "dreamed." In other words, let us place ourselves on the base AB of memory in Figure 5 on page 162, where all the events of our past life are set out in their smallest details. A consciousness which, detached from action, should thus keep in view the totality of its past, would have no reason to dwell upon one part of this past rather than upon another. In one sense, all its recollections would differ from its present perception, for, if we take them in the mul­tiplicity of their detail, no two memories are ever precisely the same thing. But, in another sense, any memory may be set along­side the present situation: it would be sufficient to neglect in this perception and in this memory just enough detail for similarity alone to appear. Moreover, the moment that the recollection is linked with the perception, a multitude of events contiguous to the memory are thereby fa stened to the perception - an indefi­nite multitude, which is only limited at the point at which we choose to stop it. The necessities of life are no longer there to regulate the effect of similarity, and, consequently, of contiguity; as, after all, everything resembles everything else, it follows that anything can be associated with anything. In the first case, the present perception continued itself in determinate movements; now it melts into an infinity of memories, all equally possible. At AB, association would provoke an arbitrary choice, and, in S, an inevitable deed.

But these are only two extreme limits , at which the psycholo­gist must place himself alternately fo r convenience of study, and which are really never reached in practice. There is not, in man at least, a purely sensori-motor state, any more than there is in him an imaginative life without some slight activity beneath it. Our psy­chicallife, as we have said, oscillates normally between these two extremes. On the one hand, the sensori-motor state S delineates the present direction of memory, being nothing else, in fa ct, than its actual and acting extremity; and, on the other hand, this memory itself, with the totality of our past, is continually pressing fo r­ward, so as to insert the largest possible part of itself into the pres­ent action. From this double effort result, at every moment, an infinite number of possible states of memory, states figured by the sections A'B', A"B" of our diagram. These are, as we have said, so many repetitions of the whole of our past life. But each section is larger or smaller according to its nearness to the base or to the summit; moreover, each of these complete representations ofthe past brings to the light of consciousness only that which can fit into the sensori-motor state and, consequently, that which resem­bles the present perception from the point of view of the action to be accomplished. In other words, memory, laden with the whole of the past, responds to the appeal of the present state by two simultaneous movements, one of translation, by which it moves in its entirety to meet experience, thus contracting more or less, though without dividing, with a view to action; and the other of rotation upon itself, by which it turns toward the situation of the moment, presenting to it that side of itself which may prove to be the most useful. To these varying degrees of contraction corre­spond the various fo rms of association by similarity.

Everything happens, then, as though our recollections were repeated an infinite number of times in these many possible reduc­tions of our past life. They take a more common fo rm when memory shrinks most, more personal when it widens out, and they thus enter into an unlimited number of diffe rent "systematizations." A word from a fo reign language, uttered in my hearing, may make me think of that language in general or of a voice which once pro­nounced it in a certain way. These two associations by similarity are not due to the accidental arrival of two diffe rent representa­tions, which chance brought by turns within the attracting influ­ence of the actual perception. They answer to two different mental dispositions, to two distinct degrees of tension of the memory; in the latter case they are nearer to the pure image, in the fo rmer, they are more disposed toward immediate response, that is to say, to action. To classify these systems, to discover the law which binds them respectively to the diffe rent "tones" of our mental life, to show how each of these tones is itself determined by the needs of the moment and also by the varying degree of our per­sonal effort, would be a difficult task: the whole of this psychology is yet unmapped, and fo r the moment we do not even wish to attempt it. But everyone is clearly aware of the existence of these laws, and of stable relations of this kind. We know, fo r instance, when we read a psychological novel, that certain associations of ideas there depicted fo r us are true, that they may have been lived; others offend us, or fa il to give us an impression of reality, because we fe el in them the effect of a connection, mechanically and arti­ficially brought about, between diffe rent mental levels, as though the author had not taken care to maintain himself on that plane of the mental life which he had chosen. Memory has then its succes­sive and distinct degrees of tension or of vitality: they are cer­tainly not easy to define, but the painter of mental scenery may not with impunity confound them. Pathology, moreover, here con­firms - by means, it is true, of coarser examples - a truth of which we are all instinctively aware. In the "systematized amnesias" of hysterical patients, fo r example, the recollections which appear to be abolished are really present, but they are probably all bound up with a certain determined tone ofintellectual vitality in which the subject can no longer place himself.

Just as there are these different planes, infinite in number, fo r association by similarity, so there are with association by contigu­ity. In the extreme plane, which represents the base of memory, there is no recollection which is not linked by contiguity with the totality of the events which precede and also with those which fo llow it. Ye t at the point in space where our action is concen­trated, contiguity brings back, in the fo rm of movement, only the reaction which immediately fo llowed a fo rmer similar perception. As a matter of fa ct, every association by contiguity implies a posi­tion of the mind intermediate between the two extreme limits. If, here again, we imagine a number of possible repetitions of the totality of our memories, each of these copies of our past life must be supposed to be cut up, in its own way, into definite parts, and the cutting up is not the same when we pass from one copy to another, each of them being in fact characterized by the particular kind of dominant memories on which the other memories lean as on supporting points. The nearer we come to action, fo r instance, the more contiguity tends to approximate to similarity and to be thus distinguished from a mere relation of chronological succes­sion: thus we cannot say of the words of a fo reign language, when they call each other up in memory, whether they are associated by similarity or by contiguity. On the contrary, the more we detach ourselves fr om action, real or possible, the more association by contiguity tends merely to reproduce the consecutive images of our past life. I t is impossible to enter here into a profound study of these diffe rent systems. But it is sufficient to point out that these systems are not fo rmed of recollections laid side by side like so many atoms. There are always some dominant memories, shin­ing points round which the others fo rm a vague nebulosity. These shining points are multiplied in the degree to which our memory expands. The process of localizing a recollection in the past, fo r instance, cannot at all consist, as has been said, in plunging into the mass of our memories, as into a bag, to draw out memories, closer and closer to each other, between which the memory to be localized may find its place. By what happy chance could we just hit upon on a growing number of intercalary recollections? The work oflocalization consists, in reality, in a growing effort of expan­sion, by which the memory, always present in its entirety to itself, spreads out its recollections over an ever wider surface and so ends by distinguishing, in what was till then a confused mass, the remem­brance which could not find its proper place. Here again, more­over, the pathology of memory is instructive. In retrogressive amnesia, the recollections which disappear from consciousness are probably preserved in remote planes of memory, and the patient can find them there by an exceptional effort like that which is effected in the hypnotic state. But, on the lower planes, these memories await, so to speak, the dominant image to which they may be fa stened. A sharp shock, a violent emotion, fo rms the deci­sive event to which they cling; if this event, by reason of its sud­den character, is cut offfrom the rest of our history, they fo llow it into oblivion. We can understand, then, that the oblivion which fo llows a physical or moral shock should include the events which immediately preceded it - a phenomenon which is very difficult to explain in all other conceptions of memory. Let us remark in passing that if we refuse to attribute some such waiting to recent, and even to relatively distant, recollections, the normal work of memory becomes unintelligible. For every event of which the rec­ollection is now imprinted on the memory, however simple we suppose it to be, has occupied a certain time. The perceptions, which filled the first period of this interval, and now fo rm with the later perceptions an undivided memory, were then really "loose" as long as the decisive part of the event had not occurred and drawn them along. Between the disappearance of a memory with its var­ious preliminary details, and the abolition, in retrogressive amne­sia, of a greater or less number of recollections previous to a given event, there is, then, merely a diffe rence of degree, not of kind.

From these various considerations on the lower mental life results a certain view of intellectual equilibrium. This equilibrium will be upset only by a perturbation of the elements which serve as its matter. We cannot here go into questions of mental pathology; yet neither can we avoid them entirely, since we are endeavoring to discover the exact relation between body and mind.

We have supposed that the mind travels unceasingly over the interval comprised between its two extreme limits, the plane of action and the plane of dream. Let us suppose that we have to make a decision. Collecting, organizing the totality of its experi­ence in what we call its character, the mind causes it to converge upon actions in which we shall afterwards find, together with the past which is their matter, the unforeseen fo rm which is stamped upon them by personality; but the action is not able to become real unless it succeeds in encasing itself in the actual situation, that is to say, in that particular assemblage of circumstances which is due to the particular position of the body in time and space. Let us suppose that we have to do a piece of intellectual work, to fo rm a conception, to extract a more or less general idea fr om the multiplicity of our recollections. A wide margin is left to fancy, on the one hand, to logical discernment on the other hand; but, if the idea is to live, it must touch present reality on some side; that is to say, it must be able, from step to step, and by progressive diminutions or contractions of itself, to be more or less acted by the body at the same time as it is thought by the mind. Our body, with the sensations which it receives on the one hand and the movements which it is capable of executing on the other hand, is then, that which fixes our mind, and gives it ballast and poise. The activity of the mind goes fa r beyond the mass of accumulated memories, as this mass of memories itself is infinitely more than the sensations and movements of the present hour; but these sen­sations and these movements condition what we may term our attention to life , and that is why everything depends on their cohe­sion in the normal work of the mind, as in a pyramid which should stand upon its apex.

If, moreover, we cast a glance at the minute structure of the nervous system as recent discoveries have revealed it to us, we see everywhere conducting lines, nowhere any centers. Threads placed end to end, of which the extremities probably touch when the current passes: this is all that is seen. And perhaps this is all there is, if it is true that the body is only a place of meeting and transfer, where stimulations received result in movements accomplished, as we have supposed it to be throughout this work. But these threads, which receive disturbances or stimulations fr om the exter­nal world and return them to it in the fo rm of appropriate reac­tions, these threads so beautifully stretched from the periphery to the periphery, are just what ensure by the solidity of these con­nections and the precision of their interweaving the sensori-motor equilibrium of the body, that is to say, its adaptation to the present circumstances. Relax this tension or destroy this equilibrium: everything happens as if attention detached itself from life. Dreams and insanity appear to be little else than this.

We were speaking just now of the recent hypothesis which attributes sleep to an interruption ofthe solidarity among the neu­rons. Even if we do not accept this hypothesis (which is, however, confirmed by some curious experiments), we must suppose, in deep sleep, at least a fu nctional break in the relation established in the nervous system between stimulation and motor reaction. So dreams would always be the state of a mind of which the atten­tion was not fixed by the sensori-motor equilibrium of the body. And it appears more and more probable that this relaxing of ten­sion in the nervous system is due to the poisoning of its elements by products of their normal activity accumulated in the waking state. Now, in every way, dreams imitate insanity. Not only are all the psychological symptoms of madness fo und in dreams - to such a degree that the comparison of the two states has become a com­monplace - but insanity appears also to have its origin in an exhaus­tion of the brain, which is caused, like normal fa tigue, by the accumulation of certain specific poisons in the elements of the nervous system.4 We know that insanity is often a sequel to infec­tious diseases, and that, moreover, it is possible to reproduce experi­mentally, by toxic drugs, all the phenomena of madness. 5 Is it not likely, therefore, that the loss of mental equilibrium in the insane is simply the result of a disturbance of the sensori-motor relations established in the organism? This disturbance may be enough to create a sort of psychic vertigo and so cause memory and atten­tion to lose contact with reality. If we read the descriptions given by some mad patients of the beginning of their malady, we find that they often fe el a sensation of strangeness, or, as they say, of "unreality," as if the things they perceived had fo r them lost solid­ity and relief.6 If our analyses are correct, the concrete feeling that we have of present reality consists, in fac t, of our conscious­ness of the actual movements whereby our organism is naturally responding to stimulation; so that where the connecting links between sensations and movements are slackened or tangled, the sense of the real grows weaker, or disappears.7

There are here, moreover, many distinctions to be made, not only between the various fo rms ofinsanity, but also between prop­erly so-called insanity and that division of the personality which recent psychology has so ingeniously compared with it.8 In these diseases of personality, it seems that groups of recollections detach themselves fr om the central memory and fo rego their solidarity with the others. But, then, it seldom occurs that the patient does not also display accompanying scissions of sensibility and of motor activity.9 We cannot help seeing in these latter phenomena the real material substratum of the fo rmer. If it be true that our intel­lectuallife rests, as a whole, upon its apex, that is to say, upon the sensori-motor fu nctions by which it inserts itself into present real­ity, intellectual equilibrium will be diffe rently affected as these fu nctions are damaged in one manner or in another. Now, besides the lesions which affect the general vitality of the sensori-motor fu nctions, weakening or destroying what we have called the sense of reality, there are others which reveal themselves in a mechani­cal, not a dynamical, diminution of these fu nctions, as if certain sensori-motor connections merely parted company with the rest. If we are right in our hypothesis, memory is very differently affected in the two cases. In the first, no recollection is taken away, but all recollections are less ballasted, less solidly directed toward the real; from this a true disturbance of the mental equilibrium arises. In the second, the equilibrium is not destroyed, but it loses some­thing of its complexity. Recollections retain their normal aspect, but fo rego a part of their solidarity, because their sensori-motor base, instead of being, so to speak, chemically changed, is mechanically diminished. But neither in the one case nor in the other are memories directly attacked or damaged.

The idea that the body preserves memories in the mechanical fo rm of cerebral deposits, that the loss or decrease of memory consists in their more or less complete destruction, whereas the heightening of memory and hallucination consists in an excess of their activity, is not, then, borne out either by reasoning or by fa cts. The truth is that there is one case, and one only, in which observation would seem at first to suggest this view: we mean aphasia, or, more generally, the disturbance of auditory or visual recognition. This is the only case in which the constant seat of the disorder is in a determined convolution of the brain; yet it is also precisely the case in which we do not find a mechanical, imme­diate and final destruction of certain definite recollections, but rather the gradual and fu nctional weakening of the whole of the affected memory. And we have explained how the cerebral lesion may effect this weakening, without the necessity of supposing any sort of provision of memories stored in the brain. What the injury really attacks are the sensory and motor regions corresponding to this class of perception, and especially those adjuncts through which they may be set in motion from within, so that memory, finding nothing to catch hold of, ends by becoming practically power­less: now, in psychology, powerlessness means unconsciousness. In all other cases, the lesion observed or supposed, never defi­nitely localized, acts by the disturbance which it causes to the whole of the sensori-motor connections, either by damaging or by breaking up this mass: whence results a breach or a simplifying of the intellectual equilibrium, and, by ricochet, the disorder or the disjunction of memory. The doctrine which makes of memory an immediate function of the brain - a doctrine which raises insol­uble theoretical difficulties - a doctrine the complexity of which defies all imagination, and the results of which are incompatible with the data of introspection - cannot even count upon the sup­port of cerebral pathology. All the fa cts and all the analogies are in favor of a theory which regards the brain as only an intermediary between sensation and movement, which sees in this aggregate of sensations and movements the pointed end of mental life - a point ever pressed fo rward into the tissue of events, and, attributing thus to the body the sole fu nction of directing memory toward the real and of binding it to the present, considers memory itself as absolutely independent of matter. In this sense, the brain con­tributes to the recall of the useful recollection, but still more to the provisional banishment of all the others. We cannot see how memory could settle within matter; but we do clearly understand how - according to the profound saying of a contemporary phi­losopher - materiality begets oblivion. 10

Your Gateway to High-Quality MP3, FLAC and Lyrics
DownloadMP3FLAC.com